Difference between revisions of "Informed consent"
m (wikify PTSD; formattings) |
m (added interwiki link) |
||
Line 710: | Line 710: | ||
[[Category:From Intactipedia]] | [[Category:From Intactipedia]] | ||
[[Category:From IntactWiki]] | [[Category:From IntactWiki]] | ||
+ | |||
+ | [[de:Einverständniserklärung]] |
Revision as of 12:12, 6 May 2022
Informed consent is a legal and ethical prerequisite for surgery and other procedures in the United States and many other nations.
It is defined as:
Assent to permit an occurrence, such as surgery, that is based on a complete disclosure of facts needed to make the decision intelligently, such as knowledge of the risks entailed or alternatives.
The name for a fundamental principle of law that a physician has a duty to reveal what a reasonably prudent physician in the medical community employing reasonable care would reveal to a patient as to whatever reasonably foreseeable risks of harm might result from a proposed course of treatment. This disclosure must be afforded so that a patient—exercising ordinary care for his or her own welfare and confronted with a choice of undergoing the proposed treatment, alternative treatment, or none at all—can intelligently exercise judgment by reasonably balancing the probable risks against the probable benefits.[1]
Contents
Informed consent for non-therapeutic circumcision of minor boys
A treatment decision should be guided by the best interests of the child, and must balance the potential benefit over the potential harm or risk.[2]
A circumcision of a boy may be therapeutic or non-therapeutic. Therapeutic circumcision may be justified only in rare cases when the foreskin is deformed, diseased, or damaged by irreparable trauma and the apparent benefit to the patient exceeds the risks and harms.
However, the vast and overwhelming majority of circumcisions of children are performed to excise healthy, functional tissue from the body of a child who is too immature to grant consent.
The Bioethics Committee of the American Academy of Pediatrics (1995) considered the power granted to parents to grant surrogate consent for diagnosis and treatment of a child. The Committee says that a parent may give "informed permission" for investigation and treatment of disease. The difference bettween informed consent and informed permission is unclear. When a child is ill, it is the practice to allow a parent to grant informed permission for diagnostic tests and appropriate treatment.[3]
Infant boys are born with a healthy foreskin. No disease or deformity is present to be diagnosed or treated. Circumcision of an infant boy is neither a diagnostic procedure nor a treatment for disease. The limited parental surrogate powers to grant informed permission recognized by the Bioethics Committee do not extend to the granting of permission or consent for the non-therapeutic circumcision of a minor child.[3]
If the medical industry had actually followed this sound ethical guidance, then the circumcision of male infants would have ended abruptly. The medical industry has chosen to ignore this advice and allow parents to grant consent for non-therapeutic circumcision of male children, so that the physician income derived from circumcision may be maintained.
Svoboda et al. (2000) examined the ethics and legality of informed consent for non-therapeutic neonatal circumcision. With regard to ethics, they concluded:
Amputating a highly sensitive and functional part of the body is extremely intrusive and should be undertaken only in situations of extreme urgency. Neonatal circumcision as it is routinely performed in this country clearly does not satisfy this criterion. It is therefore unethical and unlawful, and no parental permission should be effective.[4]
Regarding legality, they concluded:
Consent to neonatal circumcision has not been directly considered by the the courts; therefore our analysis, out of necessity, relies on established legal precedents of cases that share common elements with neonatal circumcision. With near uniformity, these precedents indicate that any consent given for neonatal circumcision would not be valid. Court decisions are in part influenced by the culture in which they occur. However, circumcision has been gradually falling out of favor in the last few decades. When the balance of public opinion shifts to opposing the practice, the legal system will become more accepting of lawsuits and lobbying for the protection of baby boys. Consequently, the legal system will no longer be able to ignore the conflict between the practice and the legal and ethical duties of medical professionals. In the meantime, the medical community should personally reexamine the ethics of the practice.[4]
Adler (2013) considered the legality of non-therapeutic circumcision of boys. He concluded in part:
This article has addressed whether circumcision is legal, and has shown that it is not. To summarize the law, boys, like girls and adults, have absolute rights under the common law to personal security and bodily integrity, and to freedom or the autonomy to make important and irreversible decisions about their bodies that can be delayed, like circumcision, for themselves. …
… A physician's legal duty is to provide competent medical care to pediatric patients independent of their parents' desires. Thus, physicians cannot take orders from parents to operate on children for reasons having nothing to do with medicine. Parents' religious rights in turn are subordinate to their sons' absolute rights to genital integrity and autonomy, and parents cannot risk harming their children, let alone actually harm them for religious reasons. Furthermore, physicians and parents have a legal duty to protect boys from circumcision.[5]
A court of appeals in Cologne, Germany Cologne circumcision court judgment ruled in 2012 that non-therapeutic male circumcision is an assault on the child, an injury to the child, and a violation of the child's rights under the Basic Law of Germany. No American court has so ruled. Until such time as an American court issues such a ruling, non-therapeutic circumcision of children in America, driven by the financial incentive is expected to continue.
At the present time, ethics and law notwithstanding, non-therapeutic circumcisions of boys are performed with parental consent. Parents will be offered medically-unnecessary, non-therapeutic circumcision and encouraged to grant consent, the sole beneficiary being the bank accounts of the hospital and the doctor. The information supplied below is intended to inform and assist parents of boys.
The Bioethics Committee (2016) of the American Academy of Pediatrics updated its guidance on informed consent in pediatric practice, however it still does not recognize the child as a human being with rights under domestic and international law.[6]
Wasserman et al. (2019) recognized children as persons entitled to respect.
Respect is something we owe to others to demonstrate that we recognize them as persons rather than objects. Patients (including children) are persons even if they do not reason well, particularly if have a kind of agency that is capable of expressing preferences. Once way to respect persons is to acknowledge that their preferences matter, something that may require soliciting those preferences, even in cases in which it would be ethically wrong to give them what they prefer. This is because it is disrespectful, and perhaps even dehumanizing to treat preference-expressing patients as mere bystanders or obstacles to their own care.[7]
Although this may be an advance, Wasserman et al., speaking for the AAP, still do not recognize the human rights of children.
Information for parents regarding non-therapeutic circumcision of infant boys.
This section is for all parents of boys, but is addressed primarily to parents of boys who are located in the United States of America, who appear to be most uninformed or misinformed about the foreskin and circumcision. Information is not making it to parents. Studies have shown that doctors provide parents with almost no accurate or useful information about circumcision. After several generations of promotion of and near universal neonatal circumcision in the United States, most Americans are profoundly ignorant of a normal body part and its valuable functions.
Provision of relevant information
The medical trade associations, such as the American Academy of Pediatrics, the American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists, the American Academy of Family Physicians, and the American Urological Association have a primary responsibility to their fellows (members) of advancing the profitability of medical practice. Consequently their public statements regarding medically-unnecessary, non-therapeutic circumcision of boys are strongly biased in favor of promoting the practice, so that their fellows can earn more money for the additional service of circumcision. The public statements are silent on the human rights of the child-patient and the multiple physiological functions of the foreskin. They describe "potential" benefits which are imagined benefits that cannot be proved to actually exist. They understate the risks of the surgical procedure, which can include loss of the penis and death. They are purposely silent on the foreskin's nature and functions, sexual, and psychological harms of having the most erogenous[8] part of the penis amputated. For all of these reasons, their public statements should not be used as a basis for informed consent.
Svoboda et al. {2000) commented:
Even more troubling in the common occurrence of parents being presented with the circumcision question for the first time when a mother is in labor at a hospital. Surgeon George W. Kaplan notes that "all too often the consent to circumcise is included in a sheaf of papers that the mother signs hurriedly on her way to the delivery room. No discussion has been held regarding the merits of the procedure or of the inherent risks." Kaplan characterizes this practice as "inexcusable". Raising the circumcision issue for the first time upon the mother's arrival at the hospital to give birth amounts to manipulation and coercion. Because the physician and the hospital benefit financially from the parent's decision, such a practice raises grave concerns about unethical profiteering.[4]
Physician behavior
One study showed that 40% of parents believed that their doctors failed to provide enough information, 46% reported that their doctors failed to give them any medical information at all, and 82.8% of parents regretted their decision they made within the first six months of their son’s life.[9]
Another study found that physicians were less likely to circumcise their own sons.[10] This suggests that doctors are very well aware that circumcision is a non-therapeutic surgery (in short, a ritual); but they do not appear to share this knowledge with parents.
A busy physician can supplement their income by as much as $60,000 per year from circumcision surgeries alone.[11] This incentive can cloud a physician’s judgment when it comes to providing parents with information about circumcision.
Many circumcised men, some of whom are doctors, experience a strong denial of loss which in turn fuels an emotional compulsion to repeat the trauma to normalize their loss. [12][13][14][15][16]
Pain and anesthesia
Many parents are surprised to hear that anesthetics are used in only a minority of cases.[17]
The use of local anesthetics significantly drives up the costs of surgery and the time to execute a circumcision amputation, so may not be used. When anesthetics are used, they can only reduce the pain, not eliminate it. Infants can not be given general anesthesia because of the medical risks involved. In the recent past, anesthesia was rarely used, if ever. Because of this, circumcision has always been an extremely traumatizing experience causing an array of short and long term behavioral and developmental problems[18][19][20][21][22][23][24][25][26][27][28], including altered perceptions of pain[29][30][31], posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD)[32][33][34][35], and a possibly of adult self destructive behavior.[36][37][38]
See also
External links
- Wagner, Richard.
Informed Consent
, emedicinehealth. Retrieved 22 June 2020. - (7 October 2013).
The Bioethics of the Circumcision of Male Children
. Retrieved 21 July 2020. - Costanza, Gary (28 February 2016).
Is circumcision legal? Does it matter?
, avoiceformen.com. Retrieved 23 July 2020. -
The case against circumcision
, homebirthcenter.com, Mothering Magazine. Retrieved 24 July 2020. -
The ethics of circumcision
, http://www.circumcisiondebate.org, The Circumcision Debate. Retrieved 24 July 2020.
References
- ↑
Informed conesnt
. Retrieved 27 June 2020. - ↑ Bioethics Committee, Canadian Paediatric Society. Treatment decisions for infants and children. CMAJ. 1 September 1986; 135: 447-8. PMID. PMC. Retrieved 23 July 2020.
- ↑ a b Bioethics Committee, American Academy of Pediatrics.. Informed consent, parental permission, and assent in pediatric practice. Pediatrics. February 1995; 95(2): 314-7. PMID. Retrieved 23 July 2020.
- ↑ a b c Svoboda JS, Van Howe RS, Dwyer JG. Informed Consent for Neonatal Circumcision: An Ethical and Legal Conundrum. J Contemp Health Law Policy. September 2000; 17(1): 61-133. Retrieved 22 July 2020.
- ↑ Adler PW. Is circumcision legal?. Richmond Journal of Law and the Public Interest. 2013; 16(3): 439-86. Retrieved 25 July 2020.
- ↑ Katz, Aviva L., Macauley, Robert C., Mercurio, Mark C., et al. Informed consent in decision-making in pediatric practice. Pediatrics. August 2016; 138(2): e20161484. PMID. DOI. Retrieved 24 January 2022.
- ↑ Wasserman JA, Navin MC, Vercier CJ, et al. Pediatric assent and treating children over objection. Pediatrics. November 2019; 114(5): e20190382. PMID. DOI. Retrieved 25 January 2022.
- ↑ Winkelmann RK. The erogenous zones: their nerve supply and significance. Mayo Clin Proc. 21 January 1959; 34(3): 39-47. PMID. Retrieved 21 July 2020.
- ↑ Adler R, Ottaway S, Gould S. Circumcision: We have heard from the experts; now let’s hear from the parents. Pediatrics. February 2001; 107(2): E20.
- ↑ Topp S. Why not to circumcise your baby boy. Mothering. January 1978; 6: 69-77.
- ↑ Fleiss PM (Sept 2002): What your Doctor May Not Tell You About Circumcision. New York: Warner books.
- ↑ Van der Kolk BA. The compulsion to repeat the trauma: re-enactment, revictimization, and masochism. Psychiatr Clin North Am. 1989; 12(2): 389-411.
- ↑ Goldman R. The psychological impact of circumcision. BJU Int. 1999; 83(Suppl. 1): 93-103.
- ↑ Maguire P, Parks CM. Coping with loss: surgery and loss of body parts. BMJ. 1998; 316(7137): 1086-1088. Retrieved 18 March 2011.
- ↑ Hill G. The case against circumcision. J Mens Health Gend. 20 August 2007; 4(3): 318-323.
- ↑ Goldman R. Circumcision policy: a psychosocial perspective. Paediatr Child Health. 2004; 9(9): 630-633.
- ↑ Stang MJ, Snellman LW. Circumcision practice patterns in the United States. Pediatrics. 1998; 101(6)
- ↑ Gunnar MR, Fisch RO, Korsvik S, Donhowe JM. The effects of circumcision on serum cortisol and behavior. Psychoneuroendocrinolog. 1981; 6(3): 269-275.
- ↑ Porter FL, Miller RH, Marshal RE. Neonatal pain cries: effect of circumcision on acoustic features and perceived urgency. Child Dev. 1986; 57: 790-802.
- ↑ Porter FL, Porges SW, Marshall RE. Newborn pain cries and vagal tone: parallel changes in response to circumcision. Child Dev. 1988; 59: 495-505.
- ↑ Emde RN, Harmon RJ, Metcalf D, et al. Stress and neonatal sleep. Psychosom Med. 1971; 33(6): 491-497.
- ↑ Gunnar MR, Connors J, Isensee WL. Adrenocortical activity and behavioral distress in human newborns. Dev Psychobiol. 1988; 21(4): 297-310.
- ↑ Anders TF, Chalemian RJ. The effects of circumcision on sleep-wake states in human neonates. Psychosom Med. 1974; 36(2): 174-179.
- ↑ Marshall RE, Stratton WC, Moore JA, et al. Circumcision I: effects upon newborn behavior. Infant Behavior and Development. 1980; 3: 1-14.
- ↑ Marshall RE, Porter FL, Rogers AG, et al. Circumcision: II: effects upon mother-infant interaction. Early Hum Dev. 1982; 7(4): 367-374.
- ↑ Lee N. Circumcision and breastfeeding. J Hum Lact. 2000; 16(4): 295.
- ↑ Anand KJS, Hickey PR. Pain and its effects in the human neonate and fetus. New Engl J Med. 1987; 317(21): 1321-1329. Retrieved 21 March 2011.
- ↑ Anand KJS, Scalzo FM. Can Adverse Neonatal Experiences Alter Brain Development and Subsequent Behavior?. Biology of the Neonate. February 2000; 77(2): 69-82. Retrieved 21 March 2011.
- ↑ Taddio A, Goldbach M, Ipp E, et al. Effect of neonatal circumcision on pain responses during vaccination in boys. Lancet. 1995; 345: 291-292. Retrieved 21 March 2011.
- ↑ Taddio A, Katz J, Ilersich AL, Koren G. Effect of neonatal circumcision on pain response during subsequent routine vaccination. Lancet. 1997; 349(9052): 599-603. Retrieved 21 March 2011.
- ↑ LaPrairie JL, Murphy AZ. Neonatal Injury Alters Adult Pain Sensitivity by Increasing Opioid Tone in the Periaqueductal Gray. Front Behav Neurosci. 30 September 2009; Retrieved 21 March 2011.
- ↑ Boyle GJ, Goldman R, Svoboda JS, Fernandez E. Male circumcision: pain, trauma and psychosexual sequelae. J Health Psychol. 2002; 7(3): 329-343.
- ↑ Rhinehart J. Neonatal circumcision reconsidered. Transactional Analysis J. 1999; 29(3): 215-221.
- ↑ Ramos S, Boyle GJ (2001):
Ritual and medical circumcision among Filipino boys: evidence of post-traumatic stress disorder
, in: Understanding circumcision: A Multi-Disciplinary Approach to a Multi-Dimensional Problem. New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers. Pp. 253-270. - ↑ Menage J. Post-traumatic stress disorder in women who have undergone obstetric and/or gynaecological procedures. J Reprod Infant Psychol. 1993; 11: 221-228.
- ↑ Van der Kolk BA, Perry JC, Herman JL. Childhood origins of self-destructive behavior. Am J Psychiatry. 1991; 148: 1665-1671.
- ↑ Jacobson B, Bygdeman M. Obstetric care and proneness of offspring to suicide. BMJ. 1998; 317: 1346-1349.
- ↑ Salk L, Lipsitt LP, Sturner WQ, et al. Relationship of maternal and perinatal conditions to eventual adolescent suicide. Lancet. 1985; i: 624-627.